Skip to main content
Log in

Sisyphean science: why value freedom is worth pursuing

  • Paper in General Philosophy of Science
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The value-free ideal in science has been criticised as both unattainable and undesirable. We argue that it can be defended as a practical principle guiding scientific research even if the unattainability and undesirability of a value-free end-state are granted. If a goal is unattainable, then one can separate the desirability of accomplishing the goal from the desirability of pursuing it. We articulate a novel value-free ideal, which holds that scientists should act as if science should be value-free, and we argue that even if a purely value-free science is undesirable, this value-free ideal is desirable to pursue.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is, of course, obviously true that some of the means to a particular end can be desirable even if the end itself is not. A state of complete starvation is undesirable, but cutting out junk food from one’s diet may well be desirable, even though it is, inter alia, one of the means to the end of starvation. What we are talking about here is something stronger: not merely the desirability of taking certain actions that happen to be means to an undesirable end, but the desirability of actively pursuing the undesirable end itself.

  2. The sharpness of the distinction between epistemic and non-epistemic values has been challenged (Rooney, 1992). We believe this is a useful and important distinction, although the boundary may be vague. Constraints of space do not permit a defence of our claim here.

  3. From here on, when we use the word “values” without qualification, we are referring to non-epistemic values.

  4. In terms of the taxonomy developed in Ward (2021), we are considering values as justifying reasons for scientific choices, while remaining agnostic about whether they also function as causal effectors for those choices.

  5. There may well be three or more value-based considerations in conflict, all leading to mutually incompatible conclusions. We focus on pair-wise contestation (bifurcation) as the smallest unit of value influence in the inferential process.

  6. This does not mean that the second set of values must lead to the contradictory conclusion ~ C. It could, for example, be the case that they lead to a denial that either C or ~ C can be concluded, due to a lack of sufficient evidence.

  7. The cases of Soviet genetics and mid-twentieth century primatology are staples in the literature on values in science; for a useful introduction, see Elliott (2017).

  8. This argument is, of course, empirical, and while it may more or less hold based on contingent facts about our contemporary society, it is not obvious that it is generally true.

  9. Miller (2014) makes a similar argument, framed in terms of the notion of pragmatic encroachment.

  10. The infeasibility of the value-free end state has been argued for in numerous contexts, including vaccine safety (Goldenberg, 2021), enzyme classification (Conix, 2020), the science of well-being (Alexandrova, 2018), epidemiological modelling during the Covid-19 pandemic (Winsberg et al., 2020), and especially climate science (Havstad & Brown, 2017; John, 2015; Frisch, 2020; Winsberg, 2012). Hoyningen-Huene (2023) argues that the inductive risk argument does not pose a serious threat to the objectivity of science.

  11. For further discussion of this critique, see Intemann (2005), Kourany (2008) and Hicks (2018).

  12. A similar point is made in de Melo-Martin and Intemann (2016).

  13. See also Boulicault and Schroeder (2021) for discussion of this strategy.

  14. This objection has been pressed by several authors. Steele (2012) notes that in complex domains deferral would require complicated reports which would mitigate their policy-relevance, Elliott (2011) argues that the deferral strategy is harmful because it involves ‘passing the buck’ to decision-makers who must formulate policy, and Steel (2016) and Brown (2019) argue that the deferral strategy renders science practically inconsequential. Frisch (2020) argues for a ‘no-buck-passing’ principle for science.

  15. Our thanks to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting these examples.

  16. It is, of course, true that one could still describe this larger scale process as constrained minimization. Trivially, any elimination strategy in the real world could also be described as constrained minimization, as there are always normative constraints restricting how we can pursue elimination. No one would suggest, for instance, that the goal of poverty elimination be fulfilled by bringing about the extinction of humanity. We do not take this to mean that we should never talk about a search strategy as aiming at elimination rather than minimization.

  17. Ruphy (2006) defends a similar argument.

References

  • Adamson, P., & Ganeri J. (2020). Classical Indian philosophy. Oxford University Press.

  • Alexandrova, A. (2018). Can the science of well-being be objective? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69(2), 421–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2004). Uses of value judgments in science: A general argument, with lessons from a case study of feminist research on divorce. Hypatia, 19(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, T. (1998). Poverty in Europe. Blackwell.

  • Betz, G. (2013). In defence of the value free ideal. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 3, 207–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boulicault, M., & Schroeder, A. (2021). Public trust in science: Exploring the idiosyncrasy-free ideal. In K. Vallier & M. Weber (Eds.), Social trust. Routledge.

  • Bright, L. K. (2018). Du Bois’ democratic defence of the value free ideal. Synthese, 195, 2227–2245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. J. (2013). Values in science beyond underdetermination and inductive risk. Philosophy of Science, 80, 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. J. (2019). Is science really value free and objective? From objectivity to scientific integrity. In K. McCain, & K. Kampourakis (Eds.), What is scientific knowledge? An introduction to contemporary epistemology of science (pp. 226–242). Routledge.

  • Camus, A. (1942[1955]). Le mythe de Sisyphe. Gallimard.

  • Conix, S. (2020). Enzyme classification and the entanglement of values and epistemic standards. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 84, 37–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Melo-Martin, I., & Intemann, K. (2016). The risk of using inductive risk to challenge the value-free ideal. Philosophy of Science, 83(4), 500–520.

  • Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67(4), 559–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Douglas, H., & Elliott, K. (2022). Addressing the reproducibility crisis: A response to Hudson. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 53, 1–9.

  • Elliott, K. (2011). Is a little pollution good for you? Incorporating societal values in environmental research. Oxford University Press.

  • Elliott, K. (2017). A tapestry of values: An introduction to values in science. Oxford University Press.

  • Frisch, M. (2020). Uncertainties, values, and climate targets. Philosophy of Science, 87(5), 979–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, M. (2021). Vaccine hesitancy: Public trust, expertise, and the war on science. University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Hacking, I. (1988). Origins of randomization in experimental design. Isis, 79(3), 427–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Havstad, J. C., & Brown, M. J. (2017). Inductive risk, deferred decisions, and climate science advising. In K. Elliott, & T. Richards (Eds.), Exploring inductive risk: Case studies of values in science (pp. 101–126). Oxford University Press.

  • Hicks, D. J. (2018). Inductive risk and regulatory toxicology: A comment on de Melo-Martín and Intemann. Philosophy of Science, 85(1), 164–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2023). Objectivity, value-free science, and inductive risk. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 13, 14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Intemann, K. (2005). Feminism, underdetermination, and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 72, 1001–1012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1956). Valuation and acceptance of scientific hypotheses. Philosophy of Science, 23(3), 237–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • John, S. (2015). The example of the IPCC does not vindicate the value free ideal: A response to Gregor Betz. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 5, 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, J. A. (2008). Replacing the ideal of value-free science. In M. Carrier, D. Howard, & J. A. Kourany (Eds.), The challenge of the social and the pressure of practice: Science and values revisited (pp. 87–111). University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Lacey, H. (1999). Is science value free? Values and scientific understanding. Routledge.

  • Larroulet Philippi, C. (2020). Well-ordered science’s basic problem. Philosophy of Science, 87(2), 365–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge. Princeton University Press.

  • Longino, H. (2002). The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press.

  • Longino, H. (2004). How values can be good for science. In P. Machamer & G. Walters (Eds.), Science, values, and objectivity (pp. 127–142). University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Miller, B. (2014). Science, values, and pragmatic encroachment on knowledge. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 4(2), 253–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Proctor, R. N. (1991). Value free science: Purity and power in modern knowledge. Harvard University Press.

  • Rooney, P. (1992). On values in science: Is the epistemic/non-epistemic distinction useful? In D. Hull, M. Forbes, & K. Okruhlik (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1992 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Philosophy of Science Association.

  • Rudner, R. (1953). The scientist qua scientist makes value judgements. Philosophy of Science, 20(1), 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruphy, S. (2006). Empiricism all the way down: A defense of the value-neutrality of science in response to Helen Longino’s contextual empiricism. Perspectives on Science, 14(2), 189–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, S.A. (2021). Democratic values: A better foundation for public trust in science. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 72(2), 545–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Belknap.

  • Steel, D. (2016). Climate change and second-order uncertainty: Defending a generalized, normative, and structural argument from inductive risk. Perspectives on Science, 24(6), 696–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steele, K. (2012). The scientist qua policy advisor makes value judgments. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 893–904.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, Z. B. (2021). On value-laden science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 85, 54–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2012). Values and uncertainties in the predictions of global climate models. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 22(2), 111–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E., Brennan, J., & Surprenant, C. W. (2020). How government leaders violated their epistemic duties during the SARS-CoV-2 Crisis. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 30(4), 215–242.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to Cristian Larroulet Philippi, Adrian Erasmus, Hamed Tabatabaei Ghomi, Sophia Crüwell, Ina Jäntgen, Zinhle Mncube, Adrià Segarra, Oliver Holdsworth and Kit Patrick for helpful discussion.

Funding

The authors did not receive support from any organization for the submitted work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Both authors have contributed to the development of the argument in the work. The authors have not made discrete contributions that can be clearly distinguished.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tarun Menon.

Ethics declarations

Financial or non-financial interests

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Ethical approval

This work has no empirical component and does not raise any issues requiring ethical approval.

Informed consent

This work has no empirical component and does not involve any participants other than the authors, so considerations of informed consent do not apply.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Menon, T., Stegenga, J. Sisyphean science: why value freedom is worth pursuing. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 13, 48 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-023-00552-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-023-00552-7

Keywords

Navigation